Benjamin Geer on Fri, 9 Jun 2006 16:29:41 +0200 (CEST) |
[Date Prev] [Date Next] [Thread Prev] [Thread Next] [Date Index] [Thread Index]
Re: <nettime> ECONOMIES OF AFFECTIVITY |
Juan Martin Prada's essay reminded me of this talk that Shierry Weber Nicholsen gave a few years ago and that, to my knowledge, hasn't been published anywhere. She takes as her starting point Stjepan Mestrovic's notion of "postemotional society": "While emotions would seem to be the inviolable heart of individual subjective experience, in postemotional society they are prefabricated, simulated, manipulated externally by, say, the mass media, triggered by images. They lose their genuineness and become quasi-emotions." She then compares this with Theodor Adorno's grim assessment of emotional life in _Minima Moralia_ to the work of psychoanalytic theorists including Wilfred Bion, Christopher Bollas and Joyce McDougall. Ben -------------------- Adorno's Minima Moralia: On Passion, Psychoanalysis and the Postemotional Dilemma Shierry Weber Nicholsen September, 2002 The Postemotional Let me start with the third of the terms in my subtitle, the postemotional. The term postemotional was coined by a sociologist, Stjepan Mestrovic. When you hear what he means by it you will probably agree with me that it is somewhat misleading. But it is catchy, and it points to a problematic around emotion in contemporary subjectivity and thus links to the question of passion. Mestrovic elaborates his idea of the postemotional in his 1997 book Postemotional Society. He conceives his work as an extension of sociologist David Riesman's analysis of American culture in The Lonely Crowd (1950), thus in the tradition of studies in culture and personality. Riesman analyzed American culture in terms of inner directed and outer directed personalities. For Mestrovic, contemporary American society is the further evolution of Riesman's outer-directed society. He argues that now it is not only ideas and behavior but also emotions that are socially determined. For reasons that will not concern me today, Mestrovic calls this state of affairs "postemotional." While emotions would seem to be the inviolable heart of individual subjective experience, in postemotional society they are prefabricated, simulated, manipulated externally by, say, the mass media, triggered by images. They lose their genuineness and become quasi-emotions. The emotional spectrum becomes limited and individual "emotions" blurred. In Mestrovic's words, "Postemotionalism holds that contemporary emotions are 'dead' in the analogous sense that one speaks of a dead current versus a 'lie wire,' or a 'dead nerve' in a limb or tooth. The current is still on, the nerve is still present anatomically, but neither is functioning as it was supposed to. The result is that all of the primal passions discussed from Aristotle to Hume to the present become shadows of their former selves. Anger becomes indignation. Envy ... becomes an objectless craving for something better. Heartfelt joy is now the bland happiness represented by the 'happy meal.' Sorrow, as the manifestation of affliction, anguish, grief, pain, remorse, trials, tribulations, and sadness, is magically transformed by the TV journalist's question 'How do you feel?' (after a death of a loved one to a sniper, or a tornado, or other calamity) into the typical but vague answer 'I'm very upset.'" Mestrovic, Postemotional Society, 62-3 Complement to the prefabricated, quasi-nature of emotions is a cult of sincerity, genuineness, and quasi-therapeutic self-examination. The reality of phoniness is masked by the propaganda of the genuine. Because emotions are not only triggered but generated through the mass-media, they can not only be manipulated but serve as means of manipulation. They serve this purpose all the better in that individuals find themselves pressed to consider their preformed emotions their very own, genuine and sincere expressions of self. Mestrovic's idea has a very disturbing implication. For the individual in such a society is in the grips of what I will call "the postemotional dilemma." What do I make of what seems to be my subjective experience? How do I know what is real? How and where can truly genuine emotional experience survive? And on what basis can I make these assertions of external manipulation? Mestrovic does not speak directly to this dilemma, but Adorno does. My focus today will be on how Adorno formulates and addresses this postemotional dilemma. For Mestrovic, "America" exemplifies postemotional society in its most advanced form. His work thus also figures in the tradition of cultural criticism through a description of American society. This tradition includes Riesman's work as well de Toqueville's and Veblen's and Adorno's. Minima Moralia and Postemotional Society Adorno wrote Minima Moralia, the work I will focus on today, while in exile in the United States in the 1940s. (Minima Moralia, note, predates Mestrovic's book by some 50 years, though it is roughly contemporaneous with Riesman's.) He had left Nazi Germany is 1934 and arrived in America in 1938, moving from New York to Los Angeles in the early 1940s, returning to Frankfurt in the early 1950s. Some of his now bestknown and influential works were written during his American exile The Authoritarian Personality, Dialectic of the Enlightenment, and Minima Moralia. First published in German in 1951, Minima Moralia is a collection of what might be described as aphoristic essays. It consists of 247 such pieces, organized into three parts, dated 1944, 1945, and 1946-47 thus written during the Second World War and continued in its immediate aftermath. The full title, Minima Moralia, Reflections from Damaged Life, refers in antithesis to Aristotle's Magna Moralia and his concern with the nature of the good life. Minima Moralia is Adorno's reflection on the thinking individual's existence in exile, during Fascism, in capitalist society in its particular American form in the 1940s -- the thinking individual who retains some intuition of "the good life" in the midst of a constellation of power, individual and society that reduces the very idea of the good life to a mere glimmer. For Adorno, the phenomena Mestrovic described were already in full swi= ng in the 1940s, and Minima Moralia explores the dialectic of the individual in postemotional society from the point of view of an individual struggling to retain the capacity to think. Of all Adorno's works, it is the one written most directly from the point of view of subjective experience, his own and perhaps for that reason the most popular. I want to start with some excerpts from one of the pieces in Minima Moralia. This is how Adorno speaks to the dilemma of the individual in postemotional society: "There is nothing innocuous left. The little pleasures, expressions of life that seemed exempt from the responsibility of thought, not only have an element of defiant silliness, of callous refusal to see, but directly serve their diametrical opposite." Adorno takes it as a given that contemporary society is one of social domination. Hence participation in the surface of "ordinary" social life, daily life, acts to legitimize the injustice and suffering beneath it. Hence "Mistrust is called for in face of all spontaneity, impetuosity, all letting oneself go, for it implies pliancy towards the superior might of the existent. The malignant deeper meaning of ease, once confined to the toasts of conviviality, has long since spread to more appealing impulses...= ." The very use of language, the medium of social life, carries the dange= r of becoming an act of complicity: "Sociability itself connives at injustice by pretending that in this chill world we can still talk to each other, and the casual, amiable remark contributes to perpetuating silence, in that the concessions made to the interlocutor debase him once more in the person of speaker. The chance conversation in the train, when, to avoid dispute, one consents to a few statements that one knows ultimately to implicate murder, is already a betrayal; no thought is immune against communication, and to utter it in the wrong place and in wrong agreement is enough to undermine its truth." Adorno names this false sociability "affability" one of the essential quasi-emotional expressions of postemotional society: "The evil principle that was always latent in affability unfurls its full bestiality in the egalitarian spirit. Condescension, and thinking oneself no better, are the same. To adapt to the weakness of the oppressed is to affirm in it the pre-condition of power, and to develop in oneself the coarseness, insensitivity, and violence needed to exert domination." Complicity seems unavoidable; it seems to follow from participation of= any kind: "Every visit to the cinema leaves me, against all my vigilance, stupider and worse." I note the word "stupider" here, and the mentions of thought, truth, and injustice. Elsewhere Adorno will refer to the intellectual and the philosopher. But Adorno is not speaking to matters of morality and intellect as distinct from matters of emotion, feeling, and human relationship. The dilemma he points to concerns the individual's life which is a personal but also a social life -- in all its aspects and as a whole: spontaneity, pleasure, communication, suffering are all implicated in the postemotional dilemma. Adorno gives us a poignant example of this destruction of the spontaneity and delicacy of human relationships in a piece on gifts and giving, called "Articles May Not Be Exchanged": "We are forgetting how to give presents . . . Real giving had its joy in imagining the joy of the receiver. It means choosing, pending time, going out of one's way, thinking of the other as a subject: the opposite of distraction. Just this hardly anyone is now able to do. At the best they give what they would have liked themselves, only a few degrees worse. The decay of giving is mirrored in the distressing invention of gift-articles, based on the assumption that one does not know what to give because one really does not want to...." "Articles May Not Be Exchanged," Minima Moralia, 42-3 The dilemma reaches down into the subtlest of expressive physical actions. The very design of the built environment entraps the individual in actions which have implications for human relations. Adorno demonstrates this in a piece about the contemporary construction of doors called "Do Not Knock": "Technology is making gestures precise and brutal, and with them men. It expels from movements all hesitation, deliberation, civility. It subjects them to the implacable, as it were ahistorical demands of objects. Thus the ability is lost, for example, to close a door quietly and discreetly, yet firmly. Those of cars and refrigerators have to be slammed, others have the tendency to snap shut by themselves, imposing on those entering the bad manners of not looking behind them, not shielding the interior of the house which receives them." "Do Not Knock," Minima Moralia, 40 If you are like me, you find these passages from Minima Moralia disturbing. On the one hand, they seem true, and it is a relief to hear someone say these things in such a direct and emphatic way. On the other hand, they seem to leave no way out. As Adorno describes it, the untruth of ordinary life is so pervasive, and complicity with domination thus so unavoidable, that Adorno the writer, and the reader along with him, are put in an untenable dilemma. All that is left is holding fast to an awareness of pain, and trying to remember that something better might have been, might conceivably still be possible: "Even the blossoming tree lies the moment its bloom is seen without the shadow of terror; even the innocent "how lovely!" becomes an excuse for an existence outrageously unlovely, and there is no long beauty or consolation except in the gaze falling on horror, withstanding it, and in unalleviated consciousness of negativity holding fast to the possibility of what is better." A particularly cruel aspect of this dilemma is that while awareness reveals a society of injustice, violence, and suffering, the postemotional dilemma means the individual is left with a solitary struggle to maintain awareness of collective suffering: "For the intellectual, inviolable isolation is now the only way of showing some measure of solidarity. All collaboration, all the human worth of social mixing and participation, merely masks a tacit acceptance of inhumanity. It is the sufferings of men that should be shared: the smallest step towards their pleasures is one towards the hardening of their pains." "How nice of you, Doctor," Minima Moralia, 25-26 This is a very disturbing thesis, and I think one of the ways we respond to the suffering Adorno seems to be proposing that we endure is to attack Adorno himself as elitist in his critique of ordinary life in postemotional society. When we think of someone as elitist, we generally attribute to that person a contempt and disdain for the other. But part of the strength of Adorno's critique is that it is written from intimate knowledge of his own complicity and his own frailty. He is no more exempt from the dilemma than anyone else. "We point at the decline of civilization into illiteracy, and ourselves forget the art of letter-writing." (27), he notes. Though his formulations are emphatic, the essayistic form, the focus on detail, and the dialectic form, work to qualify anything that might sound like absolute knowledge or definitive solution.. Just as Minima Moralia is the negative inversion of Magna Moralia, every stance proposed also has its dialectical antithesis. In fact, the piece that follows the one you just heard is called "Antithesis," and it begins this way: "He who stands aloof runs the risk of believing himself better than others and misusing his critique of society as an ideology for his private interest. While he gropingly forms his own life in the frail image of a true existence, he should never forget its frailty, nor how little the image is a substitute for true life. Against such awareness, however, pulls the momentum of the bourgeois within him. The detached observer is as much entangled as the active participant; the only advantage of the former is insight into his entanglement, and the infinitesimal freedom that lies in knowledge as such." "Antithesis," Minima Moralia, 26. Adorno's perception may seem not only elitist but also unbearably pessimistic and painful. That is a strange conjunction, for we do not think of elitists as suffering pain. But it speaks to the nature of the postemotional dilemma. From what standpoint can an individual articulate the nature of postemotional society? The defining characteristic of postemotional society is that there is no longer a mediating factor between the individual and the society. The power relations in the society as a whole shape what appears as the individual. For Adorno the individual is precisely the reflection of the totality, and increasingly the direct crystallization of social forces. "The monadological principle conceals the dominant universal," he writes (26), and "the whole is the false." Formerly, the bourgeois individual served as a mediating term. At this point in history, the thinking individual is both the last enemy of the bourgeois and the last bourgeois. (27) Adorno identifies himself with both these aspects. Adorno's friend and colleague Walter Benjamin spoke in his Theses on the Philosophy of History of a "weak Messianic power." Adorno emphasizes the frailty and weakness of his own capacities "gropingly forming his own life in the frail image of a true existence" and the "infinitesimal freedom that lies in knowledge as such." The truth of powerlessness is conjoined to the frail possibility of thought. As a "bourgeois" -- Adorno is a product of upper-bourgeois European culture in the days of its transition into fascism -- Adorno is enabled to see the more naked version of oppression in fascism and the more affable and phony version of it in America by contrast with the more nuanced version he grew up within. As the last bourgeois, and thus the product of something that is disappearing, what was positive in the nuances remains only as glimmers and memories. As the last enemy of the bourgeois, Adorno like Walter Benjamin is mindful that "the ugly movement of history is not in fact air tight," and thought needs to address itself to the remnants of the defeated, "the waste products and blind spots that have escaped...." ("Bequest," Minima Moralia, 151) Historically, Adorno is not our contemporary. But insofar as the last bourgeois is an image for the remaining capacity for individual awareness and reflection, it points to the dilemma we are all enmeshed in under the attack of the unmediated whole in postemotional society. If Adorno's formulations strike us exaggerated, dogmatic, opinionated, and repetitive, if we are irritated by the paradoxes, the negations, and the antitheses, those qualities reflect, I think, and convey to us emotionally the desperate struggle to simultaneously reflect on complicity and hold fast to the capacity for awareness and the memory and hope of something different under conditions where thinking itself is under attack, and to make that struggle visible to others similarly under attack. Adorno and Psychoanalysis Let me now turn to the second of the three terms in my subtitle: psychoanalysis. I think it is obvious that psychoanalysis as both a practice and a body of theory is relevant to the investigation of the postemotional. Psychoanalysis aims at an investigation of the deepest springs and workings of individual experience. At the same time, if a quasi-therapeutic culture is an essential part of postemotional society, no doubt psychoanalysis has played a role in its creation. For Adorno, psychoanalysis is a key endeavor in the current phase of society. But for him psychoanalysis is a crucially ambivalent enterprise. With its analysis of destructive social forces and their internalization in the individual on the one hand, and its adaptive therapeutic endeavors on the other, it manifests the same combination of progressive potential and complicity with social domination as other important human endeavors. "In psychoanalysis, nothing is true but the exaggerations," he says. To my knowledge, Adorno's familiarity with psychoanalysis is limited to Freud's work on the one hand and American adaptations of psychoanalysis on the other. All his references to psychoanalysis use Freudian terminology. He seems to have been unaware of the work of Melanie Klein and her followers in England from the 1920s on, which has important implications for an understanding of postemotionality. In Minima Moralia Adorno illuminates the way the American psychoanalysis of the time has become complicitous in postemotional society, but he also anticipates the ways in which later analysts will try to address postemotionality. We have seen Adorno's portrayal of affability is a mask of tolerance and egalitarianism that hides impersonal social violence. Its postemotional complement is an indignation that threatens violence. In Adorno's analysis, the rage the indignant person indulges represents the coercive thuggery of the social forces, and he uses portrays it in psychoanalytic terms: "If society, as a contemporary theory teaches, is really one of rackets, then its most faithful model is the precise opposite of the collective, namely the individual as monad. By tracing the absolutely particular interests of each individual, the nature of the collective in a false society can be most accurately studied, and it is by no means far-fetched to consider the organization of divergent drives under the primacy of an ego answering the reality principle as, from the first, an internalized robber band with leader, followers, ceremonies, oaths of allegiance, betrayals, conflicts of interest, intrigues and all its other appurtenances. One need only observe outbursts in which the individual asserts himself energetically against his environment, for instance rage. The enraged man always appears as the gang-leader of his own self, giving his unconscious the order to pull no punches, his eyes shining with the satisfaction of speaking for the many that he himself is. The more someone has espoused the cause of his own aggression, the more perfectly he represents the repressive principle of society. In this sense more than in any other, perhaps, the proposition is true that the most individual is the most general." "Plurale tantum," Minima Moralia, 45 In Freud's thought, the reality principle is the principle of social forces, opposed to the pleasure principle which only bows to reality under coercion. In Adorno's extrapolation the reality principle is opposed to the recognition of individuals as subjects, and to Utopian promise of happiness. The unifying forces of society acting within the individual the reality principle are ruthless gangland principles in which individuals are objects. Rage then becomes the equivalent of socially instituted violence. While Adorno's portrayal of the reality principle is perhaps consonant with Freud's view, as Marcuse would argue in Eros and Civilization, for Adorno psychoanalysis in America, as represented by American ego psychology or by the seemingly liberal work of Erich Fromm and Karen Horney, contributes directly to the ideology of the postemotional society. In his critique of American psychoanalysis, Adorno speaks as the advocate of the gaze fixed on horror and suffering. American psychoanalysis, he says, serves domination by purveying adaptation to postemotionality. It promulgates false happiness, false pleasure and the denial of suffering. The mechanization and conventionalization of pleasure, happiness, and sexuality as the signs of mental health excise, in effect, the individual's capacity for truth. Here is how Adorno makes this point: "Psychoanalysis prides itself on restoring the capacity for pleasure, which is impaired by neurotic illness. As if the mere concept of a capacity for pleasure did not suffice gravely to devalue such a thing, if it exists. As if a happiness gained through speculation on happiness were not the opposite, a further encroachment of institutionally planned behavior-patterns on the ever diminishing sphere of experience.... Prescribed happiness looks exactly what it is; to have a part in it, the neurotic thus made happy must forfeit the last vestige of reason left to him by repression and regression, and to oblige the analyst, display the indiscriminate enthusiasm for the trashy film, the expensive but bad meal in the French restaurant, the serious drink and the love-making taken like medicine as 'sex.'" "Invitation to the Dance," Minima Moralia, 62 What psychoanalysis should enable people to have is consciousness of unhappiness and pain: "As people have altogether too few inhibitions and not too many, without being a whit the healthier for it, a cathartic method with a standard other than successful adaptation and economic success would have to aim at bringing people to a consciousness of unhappiness both general and inseparable from it personal, and at depriving them of the illusory gratifications by which the abominable order keeps a second hold on life inside them, as if it did not already have them firmly enough in its power from outside." The push to deny pain demonstrates complicity with the culture industr= y and the violence underlying it: "The admonitions to be happy, voiced in concert by the scientifically Epicurean sanatorium-director and the highly strung propaganda chiefs of the entertainment industry, have about them the fury of the father berating his children for not rushing joyously downstairs when he comes home irritable from his office. It is part of the mechanism of domination to forbid recognition of the suffering it produces." (62-3) Normotic Illness In contributing to what Adorno calls "the bottomless fraud of mere inwardness," psychoanalysis is failing its own potential. In the situation of postemotionality, psychoanalysis could help to elaborate the truth of social domination that lies within neurotic pain and suffering. Notions like "normality" and "psychological health" serve to legitimize postemotionality. They serves both to mutilate the individual's capacity for experience and finding truth and to disguise the mutilation. Psychoanalysis could and should expose this. Hence Adorno's program for a psychoanalytic analysis of postemotional culture. He lays it out in a piece called "The Health unto Death": "If such a thing as a psychoanalysis of today's prototypical culture were possible; if the absolute predominance of the economy did not beggar all attempts at explaining conditions by the psychic life of their victims; and if the psychoanalysts had not long since sworn allegiance to those conditions such an investigation would needs show the sickness proper to the time to consist precisely in normality. The libidinal achievement demanded of an individual behaving as healthy in body and mind, are such as can be performed only at the cost of the profoundest mutilation... The regular guy, the popular girl, have to repress not only their desires and insights, but even the symptoms that in bourgeois times resulted from repression. Just as the old injustice is not changed by a lavish display of light, air, and hygiene, but is in fact concealed by the gleaming transparency of rationalized big business, the inner health of our time has been secured by blocking flight into illness without in the slightest altering its etiology." (58) In recent decades, psychoanalysis has begun on Adorno's program. Drawi= ng on developments in both British and French psychoanalysis, in recent years some psychoanalytic writers have described what they call "a new kind of patient" a kind of patient not anticipated by Freud, but seen more and more frequently in analysts' offices. One of those writers, Christopher Bollas, calls this new type of patient "the normotic." Writing on "Normotic Illness" in his 1987 book The Shadow of the Object, Bollas portrays a kind of patient who has succeeded in obliterating his subjective experience and the mental functions that make it up. "The normotic," he writes, "flees from dream life, subjective states of mind, imaginative living and aggressive differentiated play with the other.... We could say that if the psychotic has 'gone off at the deep end,' the normotic has 'gone off at the shallow end.' 146 What takes the place of mental life and subjective experience is things attachment to them, interest in them, identification with them. The normotic person strives to be "a commodity object in the world of human production." (136) The normotic person's sense of isolation, Bollas suggests, "is mitigated by virtue of his ability to mingle with objects and to feel identified with the commodity object world. For instance, driving a car that one is proud of may be an unconscious act of marriage. In this way, products become part of one's family, and the normotic's family of objects extends itself throughout the material object world." (155-6) The normotic is more an object than a subject. Such a person, Bollas comments, echoing Adorno's concern with the attack on thinking, "suggests that mind itself, in particular the unconscious, is an archaism, a thing to be abandoned in the interests of human progress." (156) The normotic, let me suggest, is to Bollas the psychoanalyst what the postemotional is to Mestrovic the sociologist. And Bollas is not the only analyst to address this phenomenon. Joyce McDougall, a contemporary analyst working in Paris, writes on "the anti-analysand" in her 1978 book Plea for a Measure of Abnormality. Where Bollas talks in terms of the patient experiencing himself as a commodity object, McDougall focuses on the lack of relationship. She gives us a phenomenological account of the normotic as an analytic patient, and the reaction this kind of patient generates in the analyst. McDougall describes the anti-analysand as eager for analysis and apparently having quite appropriate reasons to want analysis. Once in analysis, the anti-analysand is a faithful patient, observing all the rules, cooperating and so on. But nothing ever seems to happen. The analysis is in effect dead. McDougall speaks of the "death of curiosity" the patient has no interest in his or her self. It is the things that are missing that define the anti-analysand. The patient talks of people, and of things, but rarely of relationships between people or things. Nor does there seem to be that intermingling of conscious and less conscious layers of meaning in the patient's communication. Links between past and present, links between associations, affective links between people or indeed with the analyst or the analytic work, are absent. These patients seem to speak "a robot language impregnated with clich=E9s." (215). "In spite of better than average intelligence," McDougall says, the patient is capable of displaying a banality of thought akin to mental retardation." (225) The language is dead, and the mind is dead -- stupefied as well. How might such a condition arise? McDougall reasons that these patients, unaware of their own suffering, may have experienced something like the hospitalized infants Rene Spitz wrote of, physically cared for but emotionally so neglected that they do not develop. She compares them to patients suffering from an inability to feel physical pain, who must construct a set of automatized behavioral habits to protect themselves from disasters they cannot consciously experience as threatening. The construction of such an infallible psychic system, she writes, gives to the ego the strength of a computerized robot which in turn becomes the invincible guardian of the object's psychic life but at the price of a certain inner deadness. Survival for these patients thus means precisely making sure that no affective links are formed. But the force that cuts emotional links is an anti-life force, and this is how the analyst experiences these anti-analysands. McDougall chose the term anti-analysand over the term robot analysand with its implications of passivity, she tells us, in order to "the impression of force as implied in the concept of anti-matter, a massive strength that is only revealed through its negative effect, its opposition to the functions of cohesion and liaison." (215) Bollas too understands the genesis of normotic illness in terms of deadly forces and the "death instinct": "I think it is highly likely that the children who give in to the normotic element perceive in the parents' way of being a form of hate that we might conceptualize as a death instinct. Such a hate does not focus on the personality of the child, so it would be untrue to say that the child feels hated by the parent. It may be more accurate t say that the child experiences the parents' attack on life itself, and that such a parent is trying o squeeze the life out of existence. . . . Parent and child organize a foreclosure of the human mentality. They find a certain intimacy in shutting down life together, and in mastering existence with the unconscious skill of a military operation. Because the normotic person fails to symbolize in language his subjective states of mind, it is difficult to point to the violence in this person's being, yet it is there, not in his utterances, but in his way of shutting life out." 143 In such thinking, Bollas and McDougall are drawing on the work of Melanie Klein, who worked with very young children and who elaborated Freud's notion of the death instinct, and on post-Kleinian notions of an attack on the linking capacities of the mind. Adorno, as I have noted, was unfamiliar with the work of Klein and her followers, but his comments follow precisely this course. He draws an unforgettable picture of the deadness implicit in normotic health . I quote again from "The Health Unto Death:" "The very people who burst with proofs of exuberant vitality could easily be taken for prepared corpses, from which the news of their not-quite-successful decease has been withheld for reasons of population policy. Underlying the prevalent health is death. All the movements of health resemble the reflex-movements of beings whose hearts have stopped beating." 59 And like the Kleinians, Adorno, while using Freudian terminology, infe= rs that the psychic damage that gives rise to postemotionalism must have occurred very early on, prior to the Freudian Oedipal phase: "No science has yet explored the inferno in which were forged the deformations that later emerge to daylight as cheerfulness, openness, sociability, successful adaptation to the inevitable le, an equable, practical frame of mind. There is reason to suppose that these characteristics are laid down at even earlier phases of childhood development than are neuroses: if the latter result from a conflict in which instinct is defeated, the former condition, as normal as the damaged society it resembles, stems from what might be called a prehistoric surgical intervention, which incapacitates the opposing forces before they have come to grips with teach other...." 59 Adorno then adds the final link, to larger social dynamics in which in fact the authority of social dynamics replaces the authority of the family and programs the individual directly. This "prehistoric surgical intervention," he continues, has the result "that the subsequent absence of conflicts reflects a predetermined outcome, the a priori triumph of collective authority, not a cure effected by knowledge." (59) I find this work by Bollas and McDougall extremely interesting and valuable. And yet, if we compare it with Adorno's comments, we see that it is limited in two ways. First, perhaps understandably, as clinicians they do not make the links to the larger social level that Adorno does. And second, and more surprisingly, Adorno puts himself even more squarely within the postemotional dilemma than the clinicians do. While both Bollas and McDougall do of course make use of their own countertransference reactions -- the way the patient has affected them in their attempts to understand normotic illness -- they do not seem to feel personally threatened by the normotic. They do not raise the question of how the same forces that produced normotic illness might have affected them and their own ability to recognize what they are dealing with. Adorno, as we have seen, is much clearer that he is subjected to the same social forces that "stupefy us." These two limitations in the work of Bollas and McDougall are interrelated, and they make up the crux of Adorno's critique of psychoanalysis: that the magnitude of the death-dealing forces we see cannot be understood unless we see them in relation to the larger social order and in their impact on ourselves; but their nature is such that it is extremely difficult as individuals to reach to this understanding. Adorno articulates this critique in terms of the paradigm limiting case for conventional psychoanalytic understanding, Hitler: "The relation of knowledge to power is one not only of servility but of truth. Much knowledge, if out of proportion to the disposition of forces, is invalid, however formally correct it may be. If an =E9migr=E9 doctor sa= ys: 'for me, Adolf Hitler is a pathological case,' his pronouncement may ultimately be confirmed by clinical findings, but its incongruity with the objective calamity visited on the world in the name of that paranoiac renders the diagnosis ridiculous, mere professional preening. Perhaps Hitler is 'in-himself' a pathological case, but certainly not 'for-him.' The vanity and poverty of many of the declarations directed against Fascism by =E9migr=E9s is connected with this. People thinking in the form= s of free, detached, disinterested appraisal were unable to accommodate within those forms the experience of violence which in reality annuls such thinking. The almost insoluble task is to let neither the power of others, nor our own powerlessness, stupefy us." "Johnny-Head-in-Air," Minima Moralia, 56-57 Adorno on War and the Postemotional The experience of violence which in reality annuls free, detached, disinterested that is, non dialectical thinking: For Adorno, normotic illness and postemotionality cannot in fact be understood separately from war. If, for Adorno, unnecessary pain, suffering, poverty and degradation are the indicators of and of the destruction of experience, then death-dealing violence and social domination are the agents of this falsehood and this destruction, and thus inextricably linked to the phoniness and propaganda quality of postemotional society. Hence, for Adorno, the development of Fascism and the development of the culture industry and the other aspects of damaged life so evident in America are part and parcel of the same thing. War is thus central to Adorno's picture of the postemotional society -- not the war of the Good Americans vs. the Bad Germans, but rather the inextricable presence of killing and war-making in a society of domination. Adorno does not write much about the Second World War in Minima Moralia, but the one piece he devotes to it, "Out of the Firing Line," from summer 1944, demonstrative of his awareness of that link with a precocity that is painful to see. He speaks directly to issues which most of us have recognized more slowly, with Vietnam and post-traumatic stress syndrome, with Paul Fussell on the role of public relations and propaganda in the Second World war, with Robert Jay Lifton and the notion of psychic numbing, with the cycles of revenge, and the media management of war we are now seeing in the Middle East and between the United States and other nations. This piece is so timely that I cannot resist sharing some excerpts from it. Here is Adorno on the intertwining of business and armaments as brand-name commodities: "Reports of air-attacks are seldom without the names of the firms which produced the planes: Focke-Wulff, Heinkel, Lancaster feature where once the talk was of cuirassiers, lancers and hussars. The mechanisms for reproducing life, for dominating and for destroying it, is exactly the same, and accordingly industry, state, and advertising are amalgamated. The old exaggeration of skeptical Liberals, that war was a business, has come true: state power has shed even the appearance of independence from particular interests in profit; always in their service really, it now also places itself there ideologically. Every laudatory mention of the chief contractor in the destruction of cities, helps to earn it the good name that will secure it the best commissions in their rebuilding." And on the incommensurability of bodily, sensory experience and the mechanical and discontinuous violence of war, anticipating the obliteration of the psyche's ability to grasp and work through experience that we now call post-traumatic stress: "[T]he Second War is as totally divorced from experience as is the functioning of a machine from the movements of the body, which only begins to resemble it in pathological states.... Everywhere, with each explosion, it has breached the barrier against stimuli beneath which experience, the lag between healing oblivion and healing recollection, forms. Life has changed into a timeless succession of shocks, interspaced with empty, paralyzed intervals. But nothing, perhaps, is more ominous for the future than the fact that, quite literally, these things will soon be past thinking on, for each trauma of the returning combatants, each shock not inwardly absorbed, is a ferment of future destruction." And on the preeminence of media representation of war over the war its= elf, with consequent "withering of experience": "The total obliteration of the war by information, propaganda, commentaries, with camera-men in the first ranks and war reporters dying heroic deaths, the mishmash of enlightened manipulation of public opinion and oblivious activity; all this is another expression for the withering of experience, the vacuum between men and their fate, in which their real fate lies. It is as if the reified, hardened, plaster-cast of events takes the place of events themselves." And here is the fusion of war and administration, as can be seen in so= me of the technology of Israeli military administration of Palestinian towns: "Cinema newsreel: The impression is not of battles, but of civil engineering and blasting operations undertaken with immeasurably intensified vehemence, also of 'fumigation,' insect-extermination on a terrestrial scale. Works are put in hand, until no grass grows. The enemy acts of patient and corpse. Like the Jews under Fascism, he features now as merely the object of technical and administrative measures...." And here, finally, is Adorno on the terrible quandary of revenge, and= his vision of its endless large-scale perpetuation: "The idea that after this war life will continue 'normally', or even that culture might be 'rebuilt', is idiotic. Millions of Jews have been murdered, and this is to be seen as an interlude and not the catastrophe itself. What more is this culture waiting for? And even if countless people still have time to wait, is it conceivable that what happened in Europe will have no consequences, that the quantity of victims will not be transformed into a new quality of society at large, barbarism? As long as blow is followed by counter-blow, catastrophe is perpetuated.... If, however, the dead are not avenged and mercy is exercised, Fascism will despite everything get away with its victory scot-free, and having once been shown so easy, will be continued elsewhere. The logic of history is as destructive as the people that it brings to prominence: wherever its momentum carries it, it reproduces equivalents of past calamity. Normality is death." "Out of the Firing Line," Minima Moralia, 53-6 Adorno, Bion, and Binocular Vision "The almost insoluble task is to let neither the power of others, nor our own powerlessness, stupefy us." How can we think in such a way as to be adequate to forms of violence that transcend our previous knowledge? This is the question Adorno has set himself. His answer is demonstrated in the text that is Minima Moralia. But to conceptualize it I want to turn again to the evolution of psychoanalytic thought, and in particular to another post-Kleinian analyst, arguably the most original and far-reaching in his thinking, Wilfred Bion. Bion shares with Adorno a focus on attacks on the mind and a deep awareness of social violence, gained in part through experience in, in Bion's case, not only the second but also the first world war. During the period in which Adorno was writing Minima Moralia Bion was serving as a military psychiatrist in the British army and developing a theory of group relations through working with psychologically disabled officers in a military hospital. His work then and immediately after the end of the war was oriented to linking individual psychological phenomena to social/collective situations and to developing a theory of experience in groups and a practice of group psychotherapy. Bion was concerned with the human being's capacity to ignore reality through received knowledge and falsehood. Psychoanalytic jargon, he acknowledged, was quite capable of being used in this way. In his postwar work as a psychoanalyst, he formulated the idea that destructive forces in the mind "attacked linking," as he put it, including the links between thought and feeling and emotional bonds with another, thus preventing recognition of reality. McDougall's description of the anti-analysand draws on Bion's notion of attacks on linking. In his work with groups, Bion formulated the notion of "binocular vision." He described the irrational group fantasies that circulate within a group, such as the fantasy of an omniscient and omnipotent leader on whom group members are absolutely dependent for guidance and instruction. In his view, every individual in the group who is in any meaningful sense a member of the group is infected by the group's irrationality and participates in these group fantasies. By "binocular vision," Bion means this: as an individual within the group, I am able to perceive the fantasy-based (i.e. delusional) forces in the group because I am part of them. I feel them at work in me. At the same time, as an individual within the group, I am capable, though with great difficulty, to articulate and speak to these irrational forces, despite the risk I take that the group will turn on me. And as a socially responsible working member of the group, ( in Bion's case, as psychotherapist to the group), that is in fact my function. Bion's term "binocular vision" speaks to the terribly difficult and nearly impossible challenge of retaining a hold on thought while feeling the effect of those irrational collective forces in oneself. It formulates at the group level the dilemma of entanglement and complicity that Adorno formulates for ordinary social life in postemotional society. It is through the terribly difficult, in fact nearly impossible, exercise of binocular vision that Adorno is capable of writing Minima Moralia. Adorno and passion There is an intrinsic link between Bion's notion of binocular vision and his idea of attacks on linking. For the forces of group fantasy work to destroy the kinds of emotional and mental links that would allow one to see the complex truth of what is happening. And with this I arrive at the third of my triad of passion, psychoanalysis, and the postemotional dilemma namely, the subject of passion. I take passion to be the incompatible with postemotionality. For Mestrovic, postemotionality may very well mean "the end of passion," as he puts it. If emotions are only quasi-emotions, and are pre-formed, then they are too dead and artificial to fit the nature of passion. If we think of passion as a single intense, overpowering emotion, then Adorno's critique of postemotionality is not based on an advocacy of passion. Adorno is much more concerned with tact and nuance, the faint glimmer of possible human happiness, and with the frail capacity for critical thought. But Bion, followed by contemporary psychoanalyst Donald Meltzer, has advanced what to me is a far more interesting theory of passion. For Bion and Meltzer, passion is a form of turbulent emotional experience, a clash of competing emotional ties among themselves and with the forces that oppose and kill emotional ties. Passion provides the kind of emotional experience that genuine thought can think about. Understood this way, passion provides the fuel for personality development in the sense of the individual's expanding capacity for truth and relationship. Passion in these terms is intrinsic both to Adorno's mode of thought and to the form of his writings. It is at work in Adorno's form of binocular vision, in his struggle with the opposing sides of phenomena, and in his struggle with the deadly forces of terror and domination that would kill thought. The very act of creating links, in the face of the forces that attack linking, as Bion formulated it, is work on the side of life against death. But the linking must include the negative, recognition of the power of irrational collective forces, recognition of falsehood and oppression. The suffering inherent in damaged life is part of the fuel of Minima Moralia. The passion in Adorno's thought is also reflected in what one might call the weakly aesthetic form of Adorno's writing, a form he refers to elsewhere as constellational or configurational. For Adorno, the aesthetic dimension, as beauty and aesthetic form, is the locus of that Utopian glimmer, that faint and fleeting promise of happiness, the positive emotional link: "What beauty still flourishes under terror is a mockery and ugliness to itself. Yet its fleeting shape attests to the avoidability of terror. Something of this paradox if fundamental to all art; today it appears in the fact that art still exists at all. The captive idea of beauty strives at once to reject happiness and to assert it." "Auction," Minima Moralia, 121 This aesthetic dimension can be seen in the way in which each piece in Minima Moralia pulls together disparate levels of experience and analysis, and the way the hundreds of small essays, ranging over a wide variety of aspects of daily life, form a coherent configuration. As a piece of writing, Minima Moralia is a tour de force of linking, a product of intense passion in Bion's sense. I will end this talk with a small illustration of that idea. The piece called "Gala Dinner" is a piece on the suffocation of genuine need by the forces of production, in which the productive capacity dictates a crushing weight of consumption in which one must hurry to keep up with the new, so that for instance each bestseller must be read through from beginning to end. "Gala Dinner" begins like this: "How far progress and regression are intertwined today can be seen in the notion of technical possibilities. Mechanical processes of reproduction have developed independently of what they reproduce, and become autonomous." And ends like this: "The abundance of commodities indiscriminately consumed is becoming calamitous. It makes it impossible to find one's way, and just as in a gigantic department store one looks out for a guide, the population wedged between wares await their leader." "Gala Dinner," Minima Moralia, 118-9 The initial formulation, characteristic of Adorno's dialectical thought, points to both progressive and regressive elements in a historical phenomenon. It links technological progress with a detail of the way the productive forces are organized, the autonomy of the machines and the need for them to be kept functioning regardless of what might be the objective need for what is produced. The final formulation evokes the emotional state and the subjective experience to which Adorno has access through binocular vision -- "calamitous"; "impossible to find one's way." It couples this evocation of emotion with a double-sided analogy that links the experience of consumption to the collective political sphere and the ominous advent of terror: "Just as in a gigantic department store one looks for a guide, so the population wedged between wares awaits their leader." This is dialectical logic that incorporates subjective experience and imagination. The emotional impact, to which the final image is crucial, is what enables the dialectical analysis to hit home and be grasped. It is this passionate dimension of Adorno's thought that makes his contribution unique among social and cultural critics and gives it its particular effectiveness. References Adorno, Theodor (1974). Minima Moralia, Reflections from Damaged Life, trans. E. F.N. Jephcott. London: NLB. Bollas, Christopher (1987). The Shadow of the Object. New York: Columbia. McDougall, Joyce (1978). Plea for a Measure of Abnormality. New York: Brunner/Mazel. Meltzer, Donald (1986). "What is an Emotional Experience" and "On Turbulence." In Studies in Extended Metapsychology. Strathclyde, Perthshire: Clunie Press. Mestrovic, Stjepan (1997) . Postemotional Society. London and Thousand Oaks: Sage. Riesman, David (1950). The Lonely Crowd. New Haven: Yale. # distributed via <nettime>: no commercial use without permission # <nettime> is a moderated mailing list for net criticism, # collaborative text filtering and cultural politics of the nets # more info: majordomo@bbs.thing.net and "info nettime-l" in the msg body # archive: http://www.nettime.org contact: nettime@bbs.thing.net